Retrocausality
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Retrocausality (also called retro-causation, backward causation and similar terms) is any of several hypothetical phenomena or processes that reverse causality, allowing an effect to occur before its cause.
Retrocausality is primarily a philosophy of science thought experiment based on elements of physics, addressing the question: Can the future affect the present, and can the present affect the past?[1] Philosophical considerations of time travel often address the same issues as retrocausality, as do treatments of the subject in fiction, although the two terms are not universally synonymous.[2]
While a few legitimate scientific theories have also proposed limited forms of retrocausality, no experimental observations have been reliably reported that verify such hypotheses.[3]
Contents |
[edit] In literature
The idea of reverse causation has its origins in the self-fulfilling prophecy, a literary technique used in literature, where a prophecy itself gives birth to what it prophesies.[citation needed] Early examples of this technique include the story of Krishna in the Mahabharata, the legend of Oedipus, and several tales in the Arabian Nights such as "The Ruined Man Who Became Rich Again Through a Dream" and "The Tale of Attaf".[4]
[edit] As philosophy
Although philosophical efforts to understand causality extend back at least to Aristotle's discussions of the four causes, the idea that the arrow of time could be reversed is substantially more recent. In fact, retrocausality was long considered an inherent self-contradiction because, as 18th century philosopher David Hume discussed, when examining two related events, the cause, by definition, is the one which precedes the effect.[5]
Furthermore, the ability to affect the past suggests that causes could be negated by their own effects, creating a physical paradox,[6] such as the well-known grandfather paradox.
In the 1950s, Michael Dummett wrote in opposition to such definitions, stating that there was no philosophical objection to effects preceding their causes.[7] This argument was rebutted by fellow philosopher Antony Flew[8] and, later, by Max Black. Black's "bilking argument" held that retrocausality is impossible because the observer of an effect could act to prevent its future cause from ever occurring.[9] A more complex discussion of how free will relates to the issues Black raised is summarized by Newcomb's paradox. Essentialist philosophers have proposed other theories, such as proposing the existence of "genuine causal powers in nature"[10] or by raising concerns about the role of induction in theories of causality.[11]
More recent philosophical inquiries into the topic have often adapted aspects of modern physics, including the hypothetical tachyon particle and certain time-independent aspects of quantum mechanics. Jan Faye of the University of Copenhagen has argued that logical objections to macroscopic time travel may not necessarily prevent retrocausality at other scales of interaction.[12] Even if such effects are possible, however, they may not be capable of producing effects different from those which would have resulted from normal causal relationships.[13]
Jeanne Peijnenburg invokes retrocausality to describe how "broad imagination" can redefine or even alter past events, resulting in changes to present-day personality and perception.[14] According to Cornelis van Putten, however, there is no need to literally modify the past to achieve the results Peijnenburg discusses.[15]
[edit] As physics
Established physics does not generally employ retrocausality. Nevertheless, a number of theories allowing particles or information to travel backward in time have been proposed by respected scientists or have received meaningful evaluation by the scientific community.[citation needed]
[edit] Historical models
As the modern understanding of particle physics began to develop, retrocausality was at times employed as a tool to model then-unfamiliar or unusual conditions, including electromagnetism and antimatter.
John Archibald Wheeler and Richard Feynman proposed a theory using retrocausality and a temporal form of destructive interference to explain the absence of a type of converging concentric wave suggested by certain solutions to Maxwell's equations.[16] However, there has been no experimental observation of these "advanced waves", and it has been suggested that they may in fact simply be a different mathematical means to describe normal waves.[17]
Feynman also employed retrocausality to propose a model of the positron[18] by reinterpreting the negative-energy solutions of the Dirac equation. In this model, electrons moving backward in time would appear to possess a positive electric charge. Wheeler invoked this concept to explain the identical properties shared by all electrons, suggesting that "they are all the same electron" with a complex, self-intersecting worldline.[19] Yoichiro Nambu later applied it to all production and annihilation of particle-antiparticle pairs, stating that "the eventual creation and annihilation of pairs that may occur now and then is no creation or annihilation, but only a change of direction of moving particles, from past to future, or from future to past."[20] Although further understanding of antimatter has rendered this model largely obsolete,[21] it is still employed for conceptual purposes, such as in Feynman diagrams.
[edit] Current topics
Open topics in physics, especially involving the reconciliation of gravity with quantum physics, suggest that retrocausality may be possible under certain circumstances.
Closed timelike curves, in which the world line of an object returns to its origin, arise from some exact solutions to the Einstein field equation. Although closed timelike curves do not appear to exist under normal conditions, extreme environments of spacetime, such as a traversable wormhole[22] or the region near certain cosmic strings,[23] may allow their formation, implying a theoretical possibility of retrocausality. The exotic matter or topological defects required for the creation of those environments have not been observed. Furthermore, Stephen Hawking has suggested a mechanism which he described as the chronology protection conjecture that would destroy any such closed timelike curve before it could be used.[24] These objections to the existence of closed timelike curves are not universally accepted, however.[25]
Retrocausality has also been proposed as a mechanism to explain what Albert Einstein called "spooky action at a distance" occurring as a result of quantum entanglement. Although the prevailing scientific viewpoint is that the effects generated by quantum entanglement do not require any direct communication between the involved particles, Costa de Beauregard proposed an alternative theory.[26] At an American Association for the Advancement of Science symposium, University of Washington physicist John Cramer presented the design for an experiment to test for backward causation in quantum entanglement,[3] subsequently receiving some attention from the popular media.[27][28] Although Cramer's experiment has never been performed as of 2008, retrocausality has also been proposed as an explanation[29] for the delayed choice quantum eraser.[30]
The hypothetical superluminal particle called the tachyon, proposed in the context of the Bosonic string theory and certain other fields of high-energy physics, moves backward in time. Despite frequent depiction in science fiction as a method to send messages back in time, theories predicting tachyons do not permit them to interact with normal "time-like" matter in a manner that would violate standard causality. Specifically, the Feinberg reinterpretation principle renders impossible construction of a tachyon detector capable of receiving information.[31]
[edit] As pseudoscience
Outside the mainstream scientific community, retrocausality has also been proposed as a mechanism to explain purported anomalies, paranormal events or personal events, but mainstream scientists generally regarded these explanations as pseudoscientific.
Most notably, parapsychologist Helmut Schmidt presented quantum mechanical justifications for retrocausality,[32] eventually claiming that experiments had demonstrated the ability to manipulate radioactive decay through retrocausal psychokinesis.[33] These results and their underlying theory have been rejected by the mainstream scientific community,[34][35] although they continue to have some support from fringe science sources.[36]
Efforts to associate retrocausality with prayer healing[37] have been similarly discounted by legitimate scientific method.[38]
[edit] References
- ^ Barry, Patrick (2006-08-28). "What's done is done... or is it?". New Scientist. http://www.newscientist.com/channel/fundamentals/mg19125710.900-whats-done-is-done-or-is-it.html. Retrieved on 2006-12-19.
- ^ Faye, Jan (2001-08-27, rev. 2005-08-29). "Backward Causation". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/causation-backwards/. Retrieved on 2006-12-24.
- ^ a b Sheehan, D. P., ed. (2006-11-14). Frontiers of Time: Retrocausation - Experiment and Theory, San Diego, California, 20-22 June 2006. Record of a symposium held by the Pacific Division of the American Association for the Advancement of Science. American Institute of Physics. ISBN 0-7354-0361-9.
- ^ Irwin, Robert (2003), The Arabian Nights: A Companion, Tauris Parke Paperbacks, pp. 199–200, ISBN 1860649831
- ^ Beauchamp, Tom L. and Alexander Rosenberg (1981). Hume and the Problem of Causation. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0195202366.
- ^ Krasnikov, S. V. (Mar 1997). "Causality violation and paradoxes". Physics Review D 55 (6): 3427–3430. doi: .
- ^ Dummett, Michael (1954). "Can an Effect Precede its Cause". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supp. 28).
- ^ Flew, Anthony (1954). "Can an Effect Precede its Cause". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supp. 28).
- ^ Black, Max (1956). "Why Cannot an Effect Precede Its Cause". Analysis 16 (16): 49. doi: .
- ^ Ellis, Brian (2002). The Philosophy of Nature: A Guide to the New Essentialism. McGill-Queen's University Press. ISBN 978-0773524746.
- ^ Beebee, Helen (2006-10-25). Hume on Causation. Routledge. ISBN 978-0415243391.
- ^ Faye, Jan, Uwe Scheffler and Max Urchs, eds. (1994-10-13). Logic and Causal Reasoning. Wiley-VCH. ISBN 3050025999.
- ^ Elitzur, A., S. Doley and N. Kolenda, eds. (2005-05-25). Quo Vadis Quantum Mechanics?. Springer. ISBN 3540221883.
- ^ Peijnenburg, Jeanne. "Shaping Your Own Life". Metaphilosophy (37).
- ^ van Putten, Cornelis. "Changing the Past: Retrocausality and Narrative Construction". Metaphilosophy (37).
- ^ Wheeler, John and Richard Feynman (1945). "Interaction with the Absorber as the Mechanism of Radiation". Review of Modern Physics (17).
- ^ Price, Huw (1997-12-04). Time's Arrow and Archimedes' Point. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 0195117980.
- ^ Feynman, Richard (1949). "The Theory of Positrons". Physical Review 76 (76): 749. doi: .
- ^ Feynman, Richard. "The Development of the Space-Time View of Quantum Electrodynamics" Nobel Lecture (1965-12-11). Retrieved on 2007-01-02.
- ^ Nambu, Yoichiro (1950). "The Use of the Proper Time in Quantum Electrodynamics I". Progress in Theoretical Physics (5).
- ^ Earman, John (1967). "On Going Backward in Time". Philosophy of Science 34 (34): 211. doi: .
- ^ Thorne, Kip (1994). Black Holes and Time Warps: Einstein's Outrageous Legacy. W W Norton. ISBN 0-393-31276-3.
- ^ Gott, John Richard (2002). Time Travel in Einstein's Universe: The Physical Possibilities of Travel Through Time. Houghton Mifflin. ISBN 0-618-25735-7.
- ^ Hawking, Stephen (1992). "The Chronology Protection Conjecture". Physical Review D 46 (46): 603. doi: .
- ^ Li, Li-Xin (1996). "Must Time Machine Be Unstable against Vacuum Fluctuations?". Classical and Quantum Gravity (13).
- ^ de Beauregard, Costa (1977). "Time Symmetry and the Einstein Paradox". Il Nuovo Cimento (42B).
- ^ Paulson, Tom (2006-11-15). "Going for a blast in the real past". Seattle Post-Intelligencer. http://seattlepi.nwsource.com/local/292378_timeguy15.html?source=mypi. Retrieved on 2006-12-19.
- ^ Boyle, Alan (2006-11-21). "Time-travel physics seems stranger than fiction". MSNBC. http://www.msnbc.msn.com/id/15817394/. Retrieved on 2006-12-19.
- ^ Wharton, William R. (1998-10-28). Backward Causation and the EPR Paradox. http://arxiv.org/html/quant-ph/9810060. Retrieved on 2007-06-21.
- ^ Herzog, T. J. et al. (1995). "Complementarity and the Quantum Eraser". Physics Review Letters 75 (17): 3034–3037. doi: .
- ^ Feinberg, Gerald (1967). "Possibility of Faster-Than-Light Particles". Physical Review 159 (159): 1089. doi: .
- ^ Schmidt, Helmut (Jun 1978). "Can an effect precede its cause? A model of a noncausal world". Foundations of Physics 8.
- ^ Schmidt, Helmut (Jun 1982). "Collapse of the state vector and psychokinetic effect". Foundations of Physics 12.
- ^ Druckman, Daniel and John A. Swets, eds. (Jan 1988). Enhancing Human Performance: Issues, Theories, and Techniques. National Academy Press. ISBN 978-0309037921.
- ^ Stenger, Victor J. (May 1990). Physics and Psychics: The Search for a World Beyond the Senses. Prometheus Books. ISBN 978-0879755751.
- ^ Shoup, Richard (2002). "Anomalies and constraints: can clairvoyance, precognition, and psychokinesis be accommodated with known physics?". Journal of Scientific Exploration 16.
- ^ Leibovici, L. (2001). "Effects of remote, retroactive intercessory prayer on outcomes in patients with bloodstream infections: a controlled trial". British Medical Journal 323: 1450. doi: . PMID 11751349.
- ^ Bishop, Jeffrey P. and Victor J. Stenger (2004-12-18). "Retroactive prayer: lots of history, not much mystery, and no science". British Medical Journal 329.