Calculus of constructions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Jump to: navigation, search

The calculus of constructions (CoC) is a higher-order typed lambda calculus, initially developed by Thierry Coquand, where types are first-class values. It is thus possible, within the CoC, to define functions from, say, integers to types, types to types as well as functions from integers to integers.

The CoC is strongly normalizing, though, by Gödel's incompleteness theorem, it is impossible to prove this property within the CoC since it implies consistency.

The CoC was the basis of the early versions of the Coq theorem prover; later versions were built upon the Calculus of inductive constructions, an extension of CoC with native support for inductive datatypes. In the original CoC, inductive datatypes had to be emulated as their polymorphic destructor function.

Contents

[edit] The basics of the calculus of constructions

The Calculus of Constructions can be considered an extension of the Curry-Howard isomorphism. The Curry-Howard isomorphism associates a term in the simply typed lambda calculus with each natural-deduction proof in intuitionistic propositional logic. The Calculus of Constructions extends this isomorphism to proofs in the full intuitionistic predicate calculus, which includes proofs of quantified statements (which we will also call "propositions").

[edit] Terms

A term in the calculus of constructions is constructed using the following rules:

  • T is a term (also called Type)
  • P is a term (also called Prop, the type of all propositions)
  • If A and B are terms, then so are
    • \mathbf{(} A B )
    • (\mathbf{\lambda}x:A . B)
    • (\forall x:A . B)

The calculus of constructions has four object types:

  1. proofs, which are terms whose types are propositions
  2. propositions, which are also known as small types
  3. predicates, which are functions that return propositions
  4. large types, which are the types of predicates. (P is an example of a large type)
  5. T itself, which is the type of large types.

[edit] Judgements

In the calculus of constructions, a judgement is a typing inference:

 x_1:A_1, x_2:A_2, \ldots \vdash t:B

Which can be read as the implication

If variables x_1, x_2, \ldots have types A_1, A_2, \ldots, then term t has type B.

The valid judgements for the calculus of constructions are derivable from a set of inference rules. In the following, we use Γ to mean a sequence of type assignments  x_1:A_1, x_2:A_2, \ldots , and we use K to mean either P or T. We will write A:B:C to mean "A has type B, and B has type C". We will write B(x: = N) to mean the result of substituting the term N for the variable x in the term B.

An inference rule is written in the form

 {\Gamma \vdash A:B} \over {\Gamma' \vdash C:D}

which means

If  \Gamma \vdash A:B is a valid judgement, then so is  \Gamma' \vdash C:D

[edit] Inference rules for calculus of constructions

1.  {{} \over {} \vdash P : T}

2.  {\Gamma \vdash A : K \over 
{\Gamma, x:A \vdash x : A}}

3.  {\Gamma, x:A \vdash t : B : K \over 
{\Gamma \vdash (\lambda x:A . t) : (\forall x:A . B) : K}}

4.  {\Gamma \vdash M : (\forall x:A . B)\qquad\qquad\Gamma
\vdash N : A \over 
{\Gamma \vdash M N : B(x := N)}}

5.  {\Gamma \vdash M : A \qquad \qquad A =_\beta B \qquad \qquad B : K 
\over {\Gamma \vdash M : B}}

[edit] Defining logical operators

The calculus of constructions has very few basic operators: the only logical operator for forming propositions is \forall. However, this one operator is sufficient to define all the other logical operators:


\begin{matrix}
A \Rightarrow B & \equiv & \forall x:A . B & (x \notin B) \\
A \wedge B      & \equiv & \forall C:P . (A \Rightarrow B \Rightarrow C) \Rightarrow C & \\
A \vee B        & \equiv & \forall C:P . (A \Rightarrow C) \Rightarrow (B \Rightarrow C) \Rightarrow C & \\
\neg A          & \equiv & \forall C:P . (A \Rightarrow C) & \\
\exists x:A.B   & \equiv & \forall C:P . (\forall x:A.(B \Rightarrow C)) \Rightarrow C &
\end{matrix}

[edit] Defining data types

The basic data types used in computer science can be defined within the Calculus of Constructions:

Booleans 
\forall A: P . A \Rightarrow A \Rightarrow A
Naturals 
\forall A:P . 
(A \Rightarrow A) \Rightarrow (A \Rightarrow A)
Product A \times B 
A \wedge B
Disjoint union A + B 
A \vee B

[edit] See also

[edit] Topics

[edit] Theorists

[edit] References

  • Thierry Coquand and Gerard Huet: The Calculus of Constructions. Information and Computation, Vol. 76, Issue 2-3, 1988.
  • For a source freely accessible online, see Coquand and Huet: The calculus of constructions. Technical Report 530, INRIA, Centre de Rocquencourt, 1986. Note terminology is rather different. For instance, (\forall x:A . B) is written [x : A] B.
  • M. W. Bunder and Jonathan P. Seldin: Variants of the Basic Calculus of Constructions. 2004.
Personal tools