Legal positivism

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Jump to: navigation, search

Legal positivism is a school of thought in jurisprudence and the philosophy of law. The principal claims of legal positivism are that:

  • There is no inherent or necessary connection between the validity conditions of law and ethics or morality.
  • Laws are rules made, whether deliberately or unintentionally, by human beings.
  • Laws must follow the rules of determinism.

Contents

[edit] Legal positivism and ethics

The relation of ethics to natural law is difficult. On one hand, positivism states that there is no inherent or necessary connection between the validity conditions of law and ethics or morality. On this first account, legal positivism rejects morality as a necessary condition or foundation for law. Some philosophers have discussed another relationship between positivism and morality though. Some have suggested that morality still may have a place in positivism. Others have rejected this system. These might be called the "soft" and "hard" versions of positivism.

The soft version of positism believes that while morality cannot form the basis of a legal system, it can be declared to articulate the particulars of that system. For example, a society might legitimately say from a positivist perspective, "for this society, the rules laid down in the Old Testament are the laws." This is a system that does not depend on morality (depending rather on the authority of the person designating the Old Testament) but still incorporates morality.

Other, "hard" positivists have rejected this view. Their attacks on "soft" positivism have been of a wide variety. One criticism comes from Brian Leiter who believes that the presence of moral content in law prevents it from meeting the determinism requirement discussed below.

[edit] Legal positivism and strict interpritivism

Legal positivism should be distinguished from legal realism and such legal realists as Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr.. The differences are both analytically and normatively important.

  • Both systems believe that law is a human construct.
  • Positivists are strict textualists whereas realists, such as Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., are contextualists. Specifically, positivists attempt to remove any metaphysics from the science of law by providing a totally internally-defined system with an entirely sufficient set of meanings. Realists, on the other hand, believe the meaning of any given law only to consist of the meaning one might bring to the suggestions of the text.

The tension between positivism and realism is important. One might see this tension in a phrase by Niklas Luhmann, who argues “We can reduce... positive law to a formula, that law is not only posited (that is, selected) through decision, but also is valid by the power of decision (thus contingent and changeable).” (Luhmann, 1987) While both the the realists and the positivist will understand the human nature of the decision (and the accompanying legitimacy), the realists will find the reasoning behind that decision to be particularly and necessarily fluid, subject both at conception and interpretation to individual construction. This is not a criticism, the realist posits, but only a truism about the law. The legal positivist will, on the other hand, demand that decision to be grounded in reason, contingent on a fully recognizable set of truth-definitions, and totally consistent in meaning regardless of context.

[edit] History

[edit] Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832)

Jeremy Bentham

In English speaking philosophy, legal positivism begins with the work of Jeremy Bentham, the utilitarian philosopher. Bentham drew a sharp distinction between people he called:

  • Expositors - those who explained what the law in practice was; and
  • Censors - those who criticised the law in practice and compared it to their notions of what it ought to be.

The philosophy of law, strictly considered, was to explain the real laws of the expositors, rather than the criticisms of the censors.

Bentham was also noted for calling natural law "nonsense upon stilts."

[edit] John Austin (1790 - 1859)

The distinguishing feature of a legal system is the existence of a sovereign whose authority is recognized by most members of a society, whose authority is enforced through the use of sanctions, but who is not bound by any human superior. The criterion for validity of a legal rule in such a society is that it bears the warrant of the sovereign and will be enforced by the sovereign power and its agents.

The three basic points of Austin's positivism are:

  • the law is command issued by the uncommanded commander--the sovereign;
  • such commands are backed by threats; and
  • a sovereign is one who is obeyed by the majority

Austin viewed the law as commands from a sovereign that are backed by a threat of sanction. In determining 'a sovereign', Austin recognized it as one who society obeys habitually. This of course raises problems of the sovereign-many - Parliament, comprising numerous individuals, each with varying authoritative powers. Austin's theory also falls somewhat short in his explanations of Constitutions, International Law, non-sanctioned rules, or law that gives rights. Insofar as non-sanctioned rules and laws that allow persons to do things, for instance contract law, Austin says failure to adhere to the rules does indeed lead to sanctions, however such sanctions are in the form of "the sanction of nullity." In this way he defined law primarily in terms of the power to control others. This definition of law was criticised by the 20th century legal philosopher H. L. A. Hart, who said that it was analogous to a gunman backing up his demands with a threat of violence.

Austin was greatly influenced in his approach by Jeremy Bentham.

[edit] Hans Kelsen (1881–1973)

Kelsen's is considered a very strict and scientifically understood type of legal positivism. It is based on the idea of a Grundnorm, a hypothetical norm on which all subsequent levels of a legal system such as constitutional law and "simple" law are based. For Kelsen, "sovereignty" was a loaded concept: "We can derive from the concept of sovereignty nothing else than what we have purposely put into its definition."

His theory has followers among scholars of public law world-wide. His disciples developed "schools" of thought to extend his theories, such as the Vienna School in Austria and the Brno School in Czechoslovakia. In the English-speaking world, H. L. A. Hart and Joseph Raz are perhaps the most well-known authors who were influenced by Kelsen, though both departed from Kelsen's theories in several respects.

[edit] H.L.A. Hart (1907-1992)

H. L. A. Hart later adressed Austin. Hart liked Austin's theory of a sovereign, but felt that Austin's Command Theory failed in several important ways. In the book The Concept of Law, Hart outlined several key points: Among the many ideas developed in this book are:

  • A critique of John Austin's theory that law is the command of the sovereign backed by the threat of punishment.
  • A distinction between the internal and external points of view of law and rules, close to (and influenced by) Max Weber's distinction between the sociological and the legal perspectives of law.
  • A distinction between primary and secondary legal rules, where a primary rule governs conduct and a secondary rule allows of the creation, alteration, or extinction of primary rules. Hart specifically enumerates three secondary rules; they are:
  • The Rule of Recognition, the rule by which any member of society may check to find out what the primary rules of the society are. In a simple society, Hart states, the recognition rule might only be what is written in a sacred book or what is said by a ruler. Hart viewed the concept of rule of recognition as an evolution from Hans Kelsen's "Grundnorm", or "basic norm."
  • The Rule of Change, the rule by which existing primary rules might be created, altered or deleted.
  • The Rule of Adjudication, the rule by which the society might determine when a rule has been broken and perscribe a remedy.
  • A late reply (1994 Edition) to Ronald Dworkin, who criticized legal positivism in general and especially Hart's account of law in Taking Rights Seriously (1977), A Matter of Principle (1985) and Law's Empire (1986).

[edit] Joseph Raz (1939-)

A pupil of H.L.A. Hart, Raz has been important in continuing Hart's arguments of legal positivism since Hart's death. This included editing a second edition of Hart's 'The Concept of Law', with an additional section including Hart's responses to other philosophers' criticisms of his work.

[edit] See also

[edit] Further reading

Personal tools