Voting paradox
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
The voting paradox (also known as Condorcet's paradox or the paradox of voting) is a situation noted by the Marquis de Condorcet in the late 18th century, in which collective preferences can be cyclic (i.e. not transitive), even if the preferences of individual voters are not. This is paradoxical, because it means that majority wishes can be in conflict with each other. When this occurs, it is because the conflicting majorities are each made up of different groups of individuals. For example, suppose we have three candidates, A, B, and C, and that there are three voters with preferences as follows (candidates being listed in decreasing order of preference):
- Voter 1: A B C
- Voter 2: B C A
- Voter 3: C A B
If C is chosen as the winner, it can be argued that B should win instead, since two voters (1 and 2) prefer B to C and only one voter (3) prefers C to B. However, by the same argument A is preferred to B, and C is preferred to A, by a margin of two to one on each occasion. The requirement of majority rule then provides no clear winner.
Also, if an election were held with the above three voters as the only participants, nobody would win under majority rule, as it would result in a three way tie with each candidate getting one vote. However, Condorcet's paradox illustrates that the person who can reduce alternatives can essentially guide the election. For example, if Voter 1 and Voter 2 choose their preferred candidates (A and B respectively), and if Voter 3 was willing to drop his vote for C, then Voter 3 can choose between either A or B - and become the agenda-setter.
When a Condorcet method is used to determine an election, a voting paradox among the ballots can mean that the election has no Condorcet winner. The several variants of the Condorcet method differ on how they resolve such ambiguities when they arise to determine a winner. Note that there is no fair and deterministic resolution to this trivial example because each candidate is in an exactly symmetrical situation.
The phrase "Voter's Paradox" is sometimes[1] used for the paradox of voting, the rational choice theory prediction that voter turnout should be 0.
[edit] See also
- Kenneth Arrow, Section 1 with an example of a distributional difficulty of intransitivity + majority rule
- Arrow's impossibility theorem
- Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem
- Independence of irrelevant alternatives
- Smith set
- Social Choice and Individual Values
- Voting system
[edit] References
- ^ Follow the Trend or Make a Difference: The Evolution of Stated Opinions, pages 3 and 7, Fang Wu and Bernardo A. Huberman, HP Laboratories, September 25, 2007.